Jump to content

KJW

Senior Members
  • Posts

    401
  • Joined

  • Last visited

  • Days Won

    2

Everything posted by KJW

  1. Actually, the clock is co-moving with the cosmological fluid in both expanding space and expanding spacetime. But what @Markus Hanke is saying is that only in the expanding space does the time coordinate correspond to the proper time indicated by a clock co-moving with the cosmological fluid.
  2. No, anyone who understands the proof can see that there are no errors. It's not a difficult proof, one can work through the proof to deduce that it is correct without assuming that it is correct. Calling it "set theory math babble" doesn't bode well for your credibility on the subject. We are talking about the mathematical realm, not the physical realm. You cannot use physical reality to argue anything about mathematics. Doing so also doesn't bode well for your credibility on the subject. I think it is fair to say that in mathematics, everything exists unless it can be mathematically proven not to exist. In the case of infinite sets, we know they mathematically exist because there is no largest natural number, and therefore we have an example of an infinite set, the natural numbers.
  3. You are correct. Actually, on Page 4 of the thread "Cosmological Redshift and metric expansion", I have shown that expanding space and expanding spacetime are interconvertible by a coordinate transformation, and therefore they are actually the same thing and neither is more correct than the other.
  4. Maybe one can get rid of the "2" under the square root by some form of pulley mechanism. The problem with using dimensional analysis to derive formulae is that one can miss out on dimensionless constants, as has happened here.
  5. The list of sequences is infinite, specifically countably infinite because it is a list. It is only displayed as finite because of the limitations of illustrations. In fact, Cantor proved using set-theoretical notation that a set and the set of all its subsets (its power set) cannot be placed into one-to-one correspondence. The diagonal argument is a mere illustration of the proof for a countably infinite set. What Cantor proved is that there is an infinite sequence of distinct infinite cardinalities: natural numbers, power set of natural numbers, power set of power set of natural numbers, power set of power set of power set of natural numbers, etc. I'm not opening that. Please present it in a form that does not require opening a file.
  6. A while ago, I performed a computer simulation of the second law of thermodynamics. It involved a collection of identical entities that could be in one of two states, X or Y, with X transforming to Y and Y transforming to X at a rate governed by some rate constant. The simulation starts with all of the entities in state X, and proceeds to equilibrium. The conclusions that I drew from this simulation are: 1: The second law of thermodynamics is largely mathematical rather than physical because it is able to be simulated. 2: The rate constant is covariant with respect to time reversal. That is, it satisfies the requirement of general relativity. In other words, the thermodynamic arrow of time does not violate the principle of general relativity because the description remains valid even under time reversal. 3: The transition probability is not time reversible, applying only in the forward time direction. However, because the transition probability is based on entity counts, it is necessarily a positive number, unlike the corresponding time reversed value. 4: The transitions X to Y and Y to X in the forward time direction are not the same as the transitions Y to X and X to Y in the reverse time direction. The notion of microscopic reversibility refers to a transition and its reverse in the same time direction, not a transition in forward and reverse time directions. The transitions in the reverse time direction are not governed by transition probability. 5: Causality is governed by the transition probability and only exists in the forward time direction. The reverse time direction appears to be teleological.
  7. Thanks. However, shortly after I posted my question, I realised that you were right, at least for the original Aspect experiment involving polarisation of photons, with non-commutativity having an essential role in the experiment.
  8. Oh, man. If something is it. That is it. A logic that sometimes doesn't allow you to say this and that. That's the essence of Bell''s theorem without a doubt. I've never seen Bell's Theorem described in terms of non-commuting observables. Could you please explain how non-commuting observables relate to Bell's Theorem.
  9. Just in case you don't, an operator [math]L()[/math] is linear if and only if it satisfies: [math]L(\psi + \phi) = L(\psi) + L(\phi)[/math] Linearity is essential to QM because quantum superposition demands it.
  10. Talking about linear vs non-linear physics, below is a connection between linear quantum mechanics and non-linear classical mechanics: Klein-Gordon equation: \[\frac{1}{c^2}\frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial t^2} - \frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial x^2} - \frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial y^2} - \frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial z^2} = -\frac{m^2c^2}{\hbar^2}\psi \] \[\psi = \psi_0 exp(\frac{i}{\hbar} S(t,x,y,z))\] where [math]S(t,x,y,z)[/math] is the action. \[\frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial t^2} = \frac{\partial}{\partial t}(\frac{\partial}{\partial t} \psi_0 exp(\frac{i}{\hbar} S)) = \frac{\partial}{\partial t}(\frac{i}{\hbar} \psi_0 exp(\frac{i}{\hbar} S) \frac{\partial S}{\partial t}) = \frac{i}{\hbar} \psi_0 exp(\frac{i}{\hbar} S) \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial t^2} - \frac{1}{\hbar^2} \psi_0 exp(\frac{i}{\hbar} S) (\frac{\partial S}{\partial t})^2 = \frac{i}{\hbar} \psi \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial t^2} - \frac{1}{\hbar^2} \psi (\frac{\partial S}{\partial t})^2\] Similarly: \[\frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial x^2} = \frac{i}{\hbar} \psi \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial x^2} - \frac{1}{\hbar^2} \psi (\frac{\partial S}{\partial x})^2 \;\;;\;\; \frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial y^2} = \frac{i}{\hbar} \psi \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial y^2} - \frac{1}{\hbar^2} \psi (\frac{\partial S}{\partial y})^2 \;\;;\;\; \frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial z^2} = \frac{i}{\hbar} \psi \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial z^2} - \frac{1}{\hbar^2} \psi (\frac{\partial S}{\partial z})^2\] Thus: \[-i\hbar (\frac{1}{c^2}\frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial t^2} - \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial x^2} - \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial y^2} - \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial z^2}) + (\frac{1}{c^2}(\frac{\partial S}{\partial t})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial x})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial y})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial z})^2) = m^2c^2\] In the classical limit of [math]\hbar = 0[/math], the linear second-order Klein-Gordon equation becomes the non-linear first-order Hamilton-Jacobi equation: \[\frac{1}{c^2}(\frac{\partial S}{\partial t})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial x})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial y})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial z})^2 = m^2c^2\]
  11. KJW

    KJW Mathematics

    Klein-Gordon equation: \[\frac{1}{c^2}\frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial t^2} - \frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial x^2} - \frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial y^2} - \frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial z^2} = -\frac{m^2c^2}{\hbar^2}\psi \] \[\psi = \psi_0 exp(\frac{i}{\hbar} S(t,x,y,z))\] where [math]S(t,x,y,z)[/math] is the action. \[\frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial t^2} = \frac{\partial}{\partial t}(\frac{\partial}{\partial t} \psi_0 exp(\frac{i}{\hbar} S)) = \frac{\partial}{\partial t}(\frac{i}{\hbar} \psi_0 exp(\frac{i}{\hbar} S) \frac{\partial S}{\partial t}) = \frac{i}{\hbar} \psi_0 exp(\frac{i}{\hbar} S) \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial t^2} - \frac{1}{\hbar^2} \psi_0 exp(\frac{i}{\hbar} S) (\frac{\partial S}{\partial t})^2 = \frac{i}{\hbar} \psi \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial t^2} - \frac{1}{\hbar^2} \psi (\frac{\partial S}{\partial t})^2\] Similarly: \[\frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial x^2} = \frac{i}{\hbar} \psi \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial x^2} - \frac{1}{\hbar^2} \psi (\frac{\partial S}{\partial x})^2 \;\;;\;\; \frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial y^2} = \frac{i}{\hbar} \psi \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial y^2} - \frac{1}{\hbar^2} \psi (\frac{\partial S}{\partial y})^2 \;\;;\;\; \frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial z^2} = \frac{i}{\hbar} \psi \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial z^2} - \frac{1}{\hbar^2} \psi (\frac{\partial S}{\partial z})^2\] Thus: \[-i\hbar (\frac{1}{c^2}\frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial t^2} - \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial x^2} - \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial y^2} - \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial z^2}) + (\frac{1}{c^2}(\frac{\partial S}{\partial t})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial x})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial y})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial z})^2) = m^2c^2\] In the classical limit of [math]\hbar = 0[/math], the linear second-order Klein-Gordon equation becomes the non-linear first-order Hamilton-Jacobi equation: \[\frac{1}{c^2}(\frac{\partial S}{\partial t})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial x})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial y})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial z})^2 = m^2c^2\]
  12. KJW

    KJW Mathematics

    Klein-Gordon equation: \[\frac{1}{c^2}\frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial t^2} - \frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial x^2} - \frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial y^2} - \frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial z^2} = -\frac{m^2c^2}{\hbar^2}\psi \] \[\psi = \psi_0 exp(\frac{i}{\hbar} S(t,x,y,z))\] where S(t,x,y,z) is the action \[\frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial t^2} = \frac{\partial}{\partial t}(\frac{\partial}{\partial t} \psi_0 exp(\frac{i}{\hbar} S)) = \frac{\partial}{\partial t}(\frac{i}{\hbar} \psi_0 exp(\frac{i}{\hbar} S) \frac{\partial S}{\partial t}) = \frac{i}{\hbar} \psi_0 exp(\frac{i}{\hbar} S) \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial t^2} - \frac{1}{\hbar^2} \psi_0 exp(\frac{i}{\hbar} S) (\frac{\partial S}{\partial t})^2 = \frac{i}{\hbar} \psi \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial t^2} - \frac{1}{\hbar^2} \psi (\frac{\partial S}{\partial t})^2\] \[-i\hbar (\frac{1}{c^2}\frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial t^2} - \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial x^2} - \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial y^2} - \frac{\partial^2 S}{\partial z^2}) + (\frac{1}{c^2}(\frac{\partial S}{\partial t})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial x})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial y})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial z})^2) = m^2c^2\] In the classical limit of [math]\hbar = 0[/math], the linear second-order Klein-Gordon equation becomes the non-linear first-order Hamilton-Jacobi equation: \[(\frac{1}{c^2}(\frac{\partial S}{\partial t})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial x})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial y})^2 - (\frac{\partial S}{\partial z})^2) = m^2c^2\]
  13. 1c2∂2ψ∂t2−∂2ψ∂x2−∂2ψ∂y2−∂2ψ∂z2=−m2c2ℏ2ψ Let ψ=ψ0exp(iS(t,x,y,z)ℏ) ∂2ψ∂t2=∂∂t(∂∂texp(iS(t,x,y,z)ℏ)) \[\frac{\partial^2\psi}{\partial t^2} = \psi_0 \frac{\partial}{\partial t}(\frac{\partial}{\partial t} exp(i\frac{S(t,x,y,z)}{\hbar})) = \psi_0 \frac{\partial}{\partial t}(\frac{i}{hbar} exp(i\frac{S(t,x,y,z)}{\hbar}) \frac{\partial S(t,x,y,z)}{\partial t})\]
  14. Ok. Now I suppose you're either from Australia or a neighbourhood close to a zoo with very poor security. I meant "observer effect" is a misnomer. Probably a mild one. It's the apparatus that does it. Not consciousness. Oh, I know what you were saying. I just thought it amusing that you used the example of a koala to someone who not only lives in the country of koalas, but actually had koalas living in their backyard, and therefore has experience of koalas that even other Australians might not have. It is sad that the koalas are on longer around, but I am glad that I was able to experience them for a period of time.
  15. What mathematics are you referring to? @joigus said: which is in complete agreement with what I said.
  16. I know what a koala is. They used to be in my backyard until they disappeared as a result of urban development. I know what quantum measurement is. And I know that they are about interactions and not observation. But there is an aspect that is about observation that goes beyond the objective nature of measurement. When you asked me why we need observers, I said we don't need observers, we are observers, I don't think you understood why I said that. Being an observer does have its consequences. You can't assume that the world would run the same way without observers. Not every manifestation of significance is objectively real. For example, what in the objectively real world is the present? There are no "this is now" markers in spacetime. But as observers, we can't help but see that the present is different to the past and that the future doesn't yet exist. Where is the objective reality in that? I am saying that the collapse of the wavefunction to a single eigenvector is not objectively real and requires a conscious observer to explain. But note that there is another significant issue involved that also needs to be explained, and that is the notion of intrinsic randomness. The many-worlds interpretation explains it, the Copenhagen interpretation does not. That's not necessarily true. I do my own analyses beyond what I read. I don't necessarily accept the exact version of the many-worlds interpretation. My view is that something like the many-worlds interpretation is necessary, even if it is a modified version of the original.
  17. KJW

    Testing

    Γijk = ½ gku (∂gui/∂xj + ∂guj/∂xi – ∂gij/∂xu)
  18. If one has a conformally flat metric, the corresponding Friedmann-Lemaître-Robertson-Walker (FLRW) metric can be obtained from it by a coordinate transformation: (ds)² = A(t)² ((c dt)² – (dx)² – (dy)² – (dz)²) t = ƒ(t') ; x = x' ; y = y' ; z = z' dt = ∂t/∂t' dt' + ∂t/∂x' dx' + ∂t/∂y' dy' + ∂t/∂z' dz' = dƒ(t')/dt' dt' dx = ∂x/∂t' dt' + ∂x/∂x' dx' + ∂x/∂y' dy' + ∂x/∂z' dz' = dx' dy = ∂y/∂t' dt' + ∂y/∂x' dx' + ∂y/∂y' dy' + ∂y/∂z' dz' = dy' dz = ∂z/∂t' dt' + ∂z/∂x' dx' + ∂z/∂y' dy' + ∂z/∂z' dz' = dz' Note that the primed coordinates (t', x', y', z') and unprimed coordinates (t, x, y, z) have reversed roles compared to the earlier posts in this thread. dƒ(t')/dt' = 1/A(ƒ(t')) A(ƒ(t')) dƒ(t')/dt' = 1 Let F(t) be such that: dF–1(t)/dt = A(t) Then: dF–1(ƒ(t'))/dt' = A(ƒ(t')) dƒ(t')/dt' = 1 F–1(ƒ(t')) = t' – t'0 where t'0 is an arbitrarily chosen value of t' ƒ(t') = F(t' – t'0) Let a(t' – t'0) = A(ƒ(t')) Then: dƒ(t')/dt' = 1/A(ƒ(t')) = dF(t' – t'0)/dt' = 1/a(t' – t'0) And therefore: (ds)² = (c dt')² – a(t' – t'0)² ((dx')² + (dy')² + (dz')²) .............................. For example: (ds)² = exp(k t)² ((c dt)² – (dx)² – (dy)² – (dz)²) A(t) = exp(k t) 1/A(ƒ(t')) = dƒ(t')/dt' = exp(–k ƒ(t')) exp(k ƒ(t')) dƒ(t')/dt' = 1 (1/k) exp(k ƒ(t')) = t' – t'0 where t'0 is an arbitrarily chosen value of t' ƒ(t') = (1/k) ln(k (t' – t'0)) 1/a(t' – t'0) = dƒ(t')/dt' = 1/(k (t' – t'0)) a(t' – t'0) = k (t' – t'0) Therefore: (ds)² = (c dt')² – (k (t' – t'0))² ((dx')² + (dy')² + (dz')²) as would be expected from the earlier post.
  19. The problem with this reply is that it depends on precisely what an "unplugged" or "on" detector does to the light, the term "detector" not being sufficiently specific. It may be useful to consider the following: Suppose one places a horizontally oriented polariser in one slit, and a vertically oriented polariser in the other slit. Then there is no interference pattern even though no which-slit detection has been performed. Each photon has which-slit information by virtue of its polarisation, which is sufficient to prevent the interference pattern even when the polarisation is not measured. The quantum states from both slits are orthogonal, and there is no interference between orthogonal states. Perhaps you should also explore quantum eraser experiments. I'm quite confident about what I said... or are you telling me you can mathematically predict quantum outcomes?
  20. KJW

    Colour

    It wasn't on "The Science Forum" but on an Australian forum that hasn't been running for years. The thread was started and had run its course before I had even joined the forum. I had looked at a few posts in the thread, but I don't think I contributed to it. It was a running joke on the forum to mention this thread because of the size of it. As you can imagine, it covered every conceivable aspect of the question. I doubt that it came to any definite conclusion, though.
  21. KJW

    Colour

    On another now defunct science forum, there was a thread that was quite notable among forum members for being the longest thread in the history of the forum. It was titled: "What colour is an orange in the dark?"
  22. This thread is titled "The Observer Effect", so in order to meaningfully discuss the observer effect, one needs to distinguish between observers playing a passive role and observers playing an active role. An active role means that the conscious observer somehow affects the measurement of the quantum system so as to collapse the wavefunction. A passive role means that the quantum system affects the measuring device in a way that produces a macroscopic state that through perception affects the mind of the conscious observer. As conscious observers, we have a somewhat solipsistic subjective point of view that needs to be taken into consideration when considering an objective reality. I'm not applying any "old misguided" concept of observing. I'm certainly not suggesting that it is some kind of physical influence. Indeed, I said precisely the opposite. That is why I consider it important to distinguish between the active and passive role. I hadn't really considered whether or not the measuring apparatus is doing anything to the quantum system. Wavefunction collapse is ultimately about what the quantum system is doing to the measuring apparatus. In the many-worlds interpretation, there is no wavefunction collapse and that a superposition of quantum states leads to a superposition of measuring apparatus states which leads to a superposition of observer states. It is the superposition of observer states, entangled with the superposition of measuring apparatus states and quantum states that is the essence of the many-worlds interpretation. The role of the observer is then to answer the question: why do we not observe the superposition of observer states, measuring apparatus states, and quantum states? You've indicated that the many-worlds interpretation is not falsifiable. The reason it is not falsifiable is because the many worlds are not observable (if they were observable, there would be no question about existence). Therefore, it is about observation. At the heart of the matter is where we draw the line between objective reality and subjective observation. There is nothing in the mathematics that says that a measurement selects one eigenstate from the set of possible eigenstates. The mathematics only identifies the set of eigenstates. The selection of a particular eigenstate from the set of eigenstates is artificially imposed on the basis of observation. The mathematics ultimately implies the many-worlds interpretation, or as it was originally called, the "relative state formulation".
  23. As one attempts to separate the quarks in a proton, the force between them increases. Thus, there comes a point where there is so much energy that one or more quark-antiquark pairs are created. This results in one or more mesons being released, leaving behind some form of baryon (not necessarily a proton).
  24. Yes, the observer does have an important role, though it is a passive role. We don't need observers, we are observers. Without observers, the measuring devices would still do their thing, only there would no longer be any need for the Copenhagen interpretation. The Copenhagen interpretation suggests that it is physics that determine the particular eigenstate that we observe, whereas the many-worlds interpretation implies that it is not physics but the observer that determines the particular eigenstate that we observe, simply through the act of observation. Because the microscopic quantum state, the macroscopic state of the measurement device, all the observers observing the measurement device, and the world that contains all of these are in an entangled state. Considering Schrödinger's cat, the cat becomes entangled with the radioactive source, and when I open the box, I become entangled with the cat and the radioactive source. By becoming entangled with the cat, I no longer observe the cat state and the radioactive source state as a superposition of states. Any other observers who observe the cat becomes entangled with the same cat state as me, as well as becoming entangled with me, and therefore observes the same cat state and radioactive source state as me.
  25. It's not really an interpretation of an interpretation, but more like saying that the notion of the splitting of realities is a strawman that should not be used to reject the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics. In truth, all I am saying is that in the Born rule, all the eigenstates exist, and that it is merely a first-person perspective that gives rise to the observation of only a single eigenstate. Although I am saying that the many worlds is the ontological reality, and that the Copenhagen interpretation is the subjective observation of the many worlds, I am not claiming to fully understand the precise details of the many worlds.
×
×
  • Create New...

Important Information

We have placed cookies on your device to help make this website better. You can adjust your cookie settings, otherwise we'll assume you're okay to continue.