“There is another way of looking at this, if happiness andsuffering are linked to the impending increase and decrease of inclusive fitness(as we should expect them to be; Chapter 2), a foetus or baby that has detectedin itself some fatal physiological flaw is expected of itself to die at the earliestopportunity, and, in executing this decision, it should die relatively calmly andhappily, aware perhaps in a subconscious way that it is doing the ‘right thing’.This because for itself it has nothing to lose. By bringing the event forwards,it is helping its sibs and parents who are likely carriers of the same thanaticgene it has found occasion to express.” W.DHamilton: Narrow Roads of Gene Land (p.90)
As the above quotation makes clear, the topic in which I aminterested goes to the very heart of what it is to be a human being. That iswhy I framed my first posting cautiously. However it has been suggested to methat I am very unlikely to elicit responses unless I am more forthcoming. Sohere goes.
In suggesting that organisms are likely to carry thanaticgenes (i.e. genes coding for a contingent process of self-destruction),Hamilton focuses on resource allocation. The idea that inclusive fitness will favour any means serving to ensure thatresources available to a family group are allocated in a way most conducive tomaximising genetic throughput to the next generation.
As I have long held the view that the potentially lethallinkage between clinical depression and its physiological sequelea is almostcertainly a mechanism favoured by natural selection, Hamilton’s conjecture hasbeen of considerable intellectual comfort to me. However, it has given me littledirect help. After all, severe depression is at least as likely to afflict an independentlyfunctioning adult as it is a child. Where, then, lies the familial advantage ifa member fully capable of reproduction is prematurely removed for the genepool? Surely, its only effect would be anet reduction in the passage of genes from one generation to the next.
After years of effort, I came up with an answer which seemsto me robust to challenge. It turns on the central premise of both stockbreedingand life insurance: judge on the basis of family merits, not individual meritsalone. As every biologist knows, the reason lies in the difference between ourphenotypes and genotypes i.e. the genes we express are only part of our geneticendowment and, for better or for worse, those genes unexpressed in ourselvesare likely to appear in future generations. For species evolved to select mates this is ofmajor importance, albeit very little researched. And it carries with it avicious corollary: if a member of a kin group’s phenotype gives evidence that itskin may carry, unexpressed, many sub-optimal genes, a point may be reachedwhere its own potential gene throughput is outweighed by the reputationaldamage it inadvertently causes to the mating prospects of the other groupmembers. At this point, as with Hamilton’sembryo or neonate, its rapid elimination would work to the selective advantageof any gene which coded for such an outcome. Hence the lethal mechanism which has for so long interested me.
Given that in 1999 the World Health Organisation placedmajor depressive disorders in fourth place in terms of diseases having the mostdetrimental effects on human well-being, what I call “stigma theory” seems tome to be worthy of investigation. How, then, do I get the ball rolling?