matt grime Posted July 25, 2005 Posted July 25, 2005 yes: andrew wiles, ribet and a handful of others understand it, though no one would be able to reproduce it on demand, and no one here will understand it.
bloodhound Posted July 25, 2005 Posted July 25, 2005 I asked my number theory lecturer and he said that only one person in our university "claims" to understand the proof, and he isn't entirely convinced about that.
Dave Posted July 25, 2005 Posted July 25, 2005 I have a copy of the proof, but I'm obviously not going to be able to understand it. The problem is that a lot of number theorists have little knowledge of modular forms and vice versa. And, of course, the proof is an absolute monster using hundreds of results from all over the place. Nice to see you around again, bloodhound
swansont Posted July 25, 2005 Posted July 25, 2005 Actually the proof is quite simple. I have a truly marvellous demonstration of the proposition which this reply box is unfortunately too narrow to contain.
Dave Posted July 25, 2005 Posted July 25, 2005 Har har For a moment then, I actually thought you were being serious
swansont Posted July 25, 2005 Posted July 25, 2005 Har har For a moment then' date=' I actually thought you were being serious [/quote'] Serious, moi?
ydoaPs Posted July 25, 2005 Author Posted July 25, 2005 it seem wierd that there would be no n>2 such that [math]a^n+b^n=c^n[/math]. i don't know why, it just does. n has to be an integer, right?
matt grime Posted July 25, 2005 Posted July 25, 2005 I hope I don't regret this since it could be taken and used as ammunition by the cranks, but for results like this, results that are huge, and cannot be easily digested by one person, then we tend to think of them as being "probably" correct. THere are known results that turned out to have no correct published proof (I figured out the correct proof for one once, but i wasn't the first to find a correct proof). INdeed peer review is not infallilble by anymeans. But perhaps the more correct statement at the moment is that there are no known problems with the proof. Remember Wiles's first proof had errors in it. Today Wiles's proof has, I beleive, been extended to other nonstable cases. Devlin wrote an artilce about this in his AMS collumn. He called them "left wing proofs" meaning 'sort of fuzzy and probably correct' as opposed to 'right wing proofs' whcih he categorized as short sharp and not to be argued with. other left wing proofs are the 4 colour theorem and the classification of finite simple groups. as far as we know they are to all intents and purposes correct and no one beleives that any error which may occur will be insurmountable.
Dave Posted July 25, 2005 Posted July 25, 2005 http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Four_color_theorem Quite a nice problem, but the proof was essentially broken down into about 2,000 subcases which were brute-forced by computers. Not a very elegent way of doing it, although Wikipedia says there's been some other proof in 2004. The classification of finite simple groups is a little more abstract, but it sufficies to say that the proof of that particular theorem is about 15,000 pages long. My lecturer calls it the "Big Monster" theorem because of the sheer size of the proof.
matt grime Posted July 25, 2005 Posted July 25, 2005 the thing with the CFSG (class. fin simp grp) is that no one person knows all of it; it was a collaborative effort of very many people. so far no holes have been found. some people are sure it's true and some people are less confident. i have no knowledge of any of it and have no opinion.
jordan Posted July 25, 2005 Posted July 25, 2005 So is there a basic problem here in that the only way to learn the material contained in the proof is to talk to the guy (or guys) who proved it himself (themselves), thus running the risk of learning the material in a way biased towards the assumption that the proof is correct?
Dave Posted July 25, 2005 Posted July 25, 2005 No; you can just sit down and go through everything line by line if you wanted to look at it and prove it. It's just it's rather a lot to go through, that's all
matt grime Posted July 25, 2005 Posted July 25, 2005 no, the problem is that the amount of material is so huge in the case of CFSG (or in the original proof of the 4 colour theorem buried in computer code) that any errors in it are difficult to spot. imagine proof reading an article. If it's 1 page long you can get all the typos. If it is several thousand pages long then how confident are you that you got everything when you read it (and there are no computer spell checks)? Did you absolutely check every single other result that you used? There are other things too, and few articles are error free. Most errors are insiinficant, typos even, but in the CFSG case how sure are we that 15,000 pages contain no errors? it isn't that we presume it is correct per se. Any holes in CFSG are not important given the nature of the proof: break things up into smaller chunks, so errors are only on small scales). i think we can now safely say that FLT is ok. perhaps you are aware of the Clay millenium prize problems. the criteria for a successful solution is to be publsihed in a prestigious journal and to remain unchallenged for 18 months.
jordan Posted July 25, 2005 Posted July 25, 2005 Sorry, that last post was about Fermat's theorum, not the four-color theorum. yes: andrew wiles, ribet and a handful of others understand it
matt grime Posted July 25, 2005 Posted July 25, 2005 well, the reason so few people understand it is that few people know all the relevant background to it. it is a huge undertaking requiring very diverse knowledge. that isn't to say that someone can't read it and check it but there is a difference between knowing something and understanding it. i know many parts of mathematics, and have read the papers proving them and found no errors in them, but I do not understand them at all. Lots of maths is "if... then...." formalism, so it is possible to understand the proof (ie to check the steps leading from the if to the then) without actually understanding the whole picture sometimes. for example, I 'know' that wiles showed via galois representations that all semistable modular forms are elliptic, and whilst i may understand the words i don't know how they fit together and I am essentially repeating a slogan. very few people understand any new result in maths.
bloodhound Posted July 25, 2005 Posted July 25, 2005 My group/ring theory lecturer was going on about how big the proof classification of sim fin groups was as well. On the issue of "left wing proofs" there was an article in the "sci tech" section of The economist recently, for those who don't have a subscription, I will take a liberty of copy pasting from their online archive. --------------------------- Proof and Beauty Just what does it mean to prove something? QUOD erat demonstrandum. These three words of Latin, meaning, “which was to be shown”, traditionally mark the end of a mathematical proof. And, for centuries, a proof was exactly that: showing something by breaking it down into readily agreed-upon steps. Proving something was a matter of convincing one's peers that it has indeed been shown—no more, and no less. The rhetorical flourish of a Latin epigram also has served to indicate that the notion of proof is well understood, and commonly agreed. But that notion is now in flux. The use of computers to prove mathematical theorems is forcing mathematicians to re-examine the foundations of their discipline. Through much of the 20th century, questions of mathematical rigour were passed off to logicians and philosophers—working mathematicians have been, for the most part, content to work with an intuitive definition of proof. This notion works when each step of a proof is transparent, and can be examined by all. Proof is then just a process of reducing one big, non-obvious step, to a bunch of small, obvious ones. However, if a computer is used to make this reduction, then the number of small, obvious steps can be in the hundreds of thousands—impractical even for the most diligent mathematician to check by hand. Critics of computer-aided proof claim that this impracticability means that such proofs are inherently flawed. However, its defenders point out that some theorems that many mathematicians consider to have been proved in the classical manner also have proofs which are so long as to be uncheckable. The most famous case of this is something called the classification of finite simple groups. These are abstract objects with certain mathematical properties; the claim is that, over a 30-year span in a series of papers totalling some 15,000 pages, all possible such objects were enumerated. Though the mathematical consensus is that the classification (nicknamed the “enormous theorem”) is complete, there are sceptics who point out that the dispersed proof is essentially unverifiable. What, then, does constitute a proof in the modern age? Two recent examples of how computers have been used to prove important mathematical results illustrate how the field is changing. A colouring problem The first is the “four colour theorem”, which is perhaps the mathematical theorem most likely to bedevil a toddler. It states that any planar map (that is to say, a flat one) can be coloured with at most four colours in a way that no two regions with the same colour share a border. It was first proposed in 1852 but, despite efforts by a century's worth of mathematicians, went unproven until 1976, when Kenneth Appel and Wolfgang Haken, then of the University of Illinois, announced that they had proved the result. However, Dr Appel and Dr Haken used a computer to help them prove the result by examining about 10,000 cases. (Their proof also relied on a lot of old-fashioned gruntwork.) A new proof, in a paper just written by Georges Gonthier, of Microsoft Research, in Cambridge, England, also uses a computer. Dr Gonthier used similar techniques to those of Dr Appel and Dr Haken in his proof. However, rather than have part of the proof done by hand, and part by computer, he has automated the entire proof, and done so in such a manner that it is a formal proof. Formal proof is a notion developed in the early part of the 20th century by logicians such as Bertrand Russell and Gottlob Frege, along with mathematicians such as David Hilbert (who can fairly be described as the father of modern mathematics) and Nicolas Bourbaki, the pseudonym of a group of French mathematicians who sought to place all of mathematics on a rigorous footing. This effort was subtle, but its upshot can be described simply. It is to replace, in proofs, standard mathematical reasoning which, in essence, relies on hand-waving arguments (it should be obvious to everyone that B follows from A) with formal logic. The benefit of formal logic is that it is pure syntax. At no point does proceeding from one step to the next require understanding, let alone mathematical intuition. It is merely a matter of applying an agreed-upon set of rules (for instance, that any thing is equal to itself, or that if something is true for all members of a set of objects, it is true for any one specific object) to a set of agreed-upon structures, such as sets of objects. Formal proofs, however, never gained a foothold in the mainstream mathematical community because they are tedious—they take many steps to prove something in cases in which a mathematician might just take one. To those who would use a computer, however, they have two virtues. The first is that computers, with their tolerance for tedium, are particularly suited to writing the steps of a formal proof down. The second is that, by writing those steps down in what is called a “proof witness” instead of just announcing that a program had arrived at a true result, outsiders might gain greater confidence in a result derived from a computer. As Dr Gonthier, and other supporters of the use of computers, point out, there is no reason to think that humans are less fallible than computers when doing long computations or proofs. Indeed, the opposite might be true. The idea behind both proofs of the four colour theorem is to suppose that the theorem is violated—to assume, in other words, that there is some sort of map that requires five colours to fill in. The next step is to find the mathematically simplest versions of such maps. (What is meant by simplicity in this case is actually quite involved.) Dr Gonthier then showed that all these maps can, in fact, be re-coloured with only four colours, establishing the theorem by contradiction. The catch is that there are many such regions, which must be examined on a case-by-case basis; part of the mathematical difficulty lies in proving that the cases considered suffice to cover all possible maps, and part stems from proving that each individual case is indeed colourable with just four colours. Dr Gonthier says he is going to submit his paper to a scientific journal in the next few weeks. But he would do well not to get his hopes up about getting his paper published anytime soon. A 1998 paper which proved another long-standing conjecture using a computer, by Thomas Hales, of the University of Pittsburgh, has only recently been accepted by the Annals of Mathematics, perhaps the field's most prestigious journal, and is scheduled to be published later this year. The music of the spheres Dr Hales proved Kepler's conjecture, which is that the most efficient way to pack spheres in a box is the way grocers usually pack oranges—in a so-called “face-centred cubic lattice”—the arrangement whereby each layer of oranges is shifted so that an orange touches four oranges in the layer below. Kepler posited the conjecture in 1611, and it had long resisted efforts at proof. Indeed, Hilbert made it one of his list of the 23 most difficult and fundamental questions in mathematics, in 1900. Dr Hales proved the conjecture by using a trick different in nature to Dr Gonthier's. Rather than argue by contradiction, he reduced what was a problem about an infinite number of things (the Kepler conjecture considers an infinite number of spheres in an infinitely large space) to a statement about a finite, but very large, number of mathematical objects. He then used the computer to prove bounds about these objects, some of which, he says, can be thought of as sculptures made of cables and struts. Loosely speaking, he reduced the Kepler conjecture to a problem of considering whether, given a set of cables, which have no minimum length, but can only be stretched to a certain extent, and struts, which have a limit on how much they can be compressed, one can build a sculpture of a certain type. Dr Hales used a computer, as there were roughly 100,000 such structures that had to be considered in order to prove the Kepler conjecture. Although the Annals will publish Dr Hales's paper, Peter Sarnak, an editor of the Annals, whose own work does not involve the use of computers, says that the paper will be accompanied by an unusual disclaimer, stating that the computer programs accompanying the paper have not undergone peer review. There is a simple reason for that, Dr Sarnak says—it is impossible to find peers who are willing to review the computer code. However, there is a flip-side to the disclaimer as well—Dr Sarnak says that the editors of the Annals expect to receive, and publish, more papers of this type—for things, he believes, will change over the next 20-50 years. Dr Sarnak points out that maths may become “a bit like experimental physics” where certain results are taken on trust, and independent duplication of experiments replaces examination of a colleague's paper. Some of the movement towards that direction may be forestalled by efforts of Dr Gonthier's type to use computers to provide formal proofs and proof witnesses. It is possible that mathematicians will trust computer-based results more if they are backed up by transparent logical steps, rather than the arcane workings of computer code, which could more easily contain bugs that go undetected. Indeed, it is for this exact reason that Dr Hales is currently leading a collaborative project to provide a formal proof of the Kepler conjecture. In perhaps a more prosaic example of mathematics embracing technology, he is co-ordinating that effort using a blog called Flyspeck (the word, Dr Hales explains, means to examine closely). Why should the non-mathematician care about things of this nature? The foremost reason is that mathematics is beautiful, even if it is, sadly, more inaccessible than other forms of art. The second is that it is useful, and that its utility depends in part on its certainty, and that that certainty cannot come without a notion of proof. Dr Gonthier, for instance, and his sponsors at Microsoft, hope that the techniques he and his colleagues have developed to formally prove mathematical theorems can be used to “prove” that a computer program is free of bugs—and that would certainly be a useful proposition in today's software society if it does, indeed, turn out to be true.
CgntvFalt Posted November 13, 2005 Posted November 13, 2005 One of my professors, Chandrashekhar Khare, recently proved the level-one Serre Conjecture, which implies fermat's last theorem and is a much simpler (and shorter) proof than Dr. Wiles, however it's still not easy, by any means.http://plus.maths.org/latestnews/jan-apr05/serre/ , for anyone interested. There's a link to the proof at the bottom of that page.
Dave Posted December 8, 2005 Posted December 8, 2005 Only just seen this post. Does anybody know whether his proof has been peer-reviewed yet?
Recommended Posts
Create an account or sign in to comment
You need to be a member in order to leave a comment
Create an account
Sign up for a new account in our community. It's easy!
Register a new accountSign in
Already have an account? Sign in here.
Sign In Now