Jump to content

Recommended Posts

Posted (edited)

Proof of "Axioms" of Propositional Logic:
            Synopsis.
            Willem F. Esterhuyse.
            Abstract.
 We introduce more basic axioms with which we are able to prove some 

"axioms" of Propositional Logic. We use the symbols from my other article: 

"Introduction to Logical Structures". Logical Structures (SrL) are graphs with 

doubly labelled vertices with edges carrying symbols. The proofs are very 

mechanical and does not require ingenuity to construct. It is easy to see that in 

order to transform information, it has to be chopped up. Just look at a kid playing 

with blocks with letters on them: he has to break up the word into letters to 

assemble another word. Within SrL we take as our "atoms" propositions with 

chopped up relations attached to them. We call the results: (incomplete) 

"structures". We play it safe by allowing only relations among propositions to be 

choppable. We will see whether this is the correct way of chopping up sentences 

(it seems to be). This is where our Attractors (Repulsors) and Stoppers come in. 

Attractors that face away from each other repels and so break a relation between 

the two propositions. Then a Stopper attaches to the chopped up relation to 

indicate it can't reconnect. So it is possible to infer sentences from sentences. The 

rules I stumbled upon, to implement this, seems to be consistent. Sources differ 

asto the axioms they choose but some of the most famous "axioms" are proved.

Modus Ponens occurs in all systems.

1. Introduction.
  We use new operators called "Attractors" and "Stoppers". An Attractor ( symbol: 
"-(" OR ")-") is an edge with a half circle symbol, that can carry any relation 
symbol. Axioms for Attractors include A:AA (Axiom: Attractor Annihilation)
where we have as premise two structures named B with Attractors carrying the 
"therefore" symbol facing each other and attached to two neighbouring structures: 
B. Because the structures are the same and the Attractors face each other, and the 
therefore symbols point in the same direction, they annihilate the structures B and 
we are left with a conclusion of the empty structure. Like in: 
((B)->-(  )->-(B)) <-> (Empty Structure). 
 where "<->" means: "is equivalent to" or "follows from and vice vesa".  
A:AD reads as follows:
((A)->-(B))->-(  <->  )->-(A)  []->-(B)->-(
where "[]->-" is a Stopper carrying "therefore" relation.
 We also have the axiom: A:AtI (Attractor Introduction) in which we have a row 
of structures as premise and conclusion of the same row of structures each with an 
Attractor attached to them and pointing to the right or left. Like in: 
A B C D <-> (A)-(  (B)-(  (C)-(  (D)-(
OR:
A B C D <-> )-(A)  )-(B)  )-(C)  )-(D)
where the Attractors may carry a relation symbol.
  Further axioms are: A:SD says that we may drop a Stopper at either end of a line. 
And A:ASS says we can exchange Stoppers for Attractors (and vice versa) in a 
line of structures as long as we replace every instance of the operators. A:AL says 
we can link two attractors pointing trowards each other and attached to two 
different structures.
  We prove Modus Ponens as follows:
Line nr.  Statement                            Reason
1            B  B -> C                            Premise
2             (B)->-(  (B -> C)->-(                    1, A:AtI
3             (B)->-(  )->-(B)  []->-(C)->-(                2, A:AD 
4             []->-(C)->-(                            3, A:AA
5             (C)->-(                            4, A:SD
6             (C)->-[]                            5, A:ASS
7             C                                6, A:SD
  We see that the Attractors cuts two structures into three (line 2 to line 3). In 2 "(B -> C)" is a structure.
  We can prove AND-elimination, AND-introduction and transposition. We prove
Theorem: AND introduction (T:ANDI):
1    A  B                                Premise
2    A -(x)-(  B -(x)-(                        1, A:AtI
3    (A)-(x)-[]  (B)-(x)-[]                        2, A:ASS
4    (A)-(x)-[]  B                            3, A:SD
5    (A)-(x)-(  B                            4, A:ASS
6    (A)-(x)-(B)                            5, T:AL
where "-(x)-" = "AND", and T:AL is a theorem to be proved by reasoning 
backwards through:
1    A -(x)- B                            Premise
2    A -(x)- B -(x)-(                        1, A:AtI
3    )-(x)-(A)  []-(x)-(B)-(x)-(                    2, A:AD
4    []-(x)-(A)  )-(x)-(B)-(x)-[]                    3, A:ASS
5    A  )-(x)-(B)                            4, A:SD.
where the mirror image of this is proved similarly (by choosing to place the 
Stopper on the other side of "-(x)-").
  Modus Tollens and Syllogism can also be proven with these axioms.
  We prove: Theorem (T:O): (A OR A) -> A:
1    A -(+)- A                                                            Premise
2    (A)-(+)-((A)-(+)-(_))                                          1, truth table
3          )-(+)-(A) []-(+)-((A)-(+)-(_))-(+)-(                     2, A:AtI, A:AD
4          (A) []-(+)-((A)-(+)-(_))                                       3, A:ASS, A:SD, A:ASS
5          (A)-(+)-( []-(+)- )-(+)-(A) []-(+)-(_)-(+)-(          4, A:AtI, A:AD
6          (A)-(+)-( )-(+)-(A) []-(+)-(_)-(+)-(                      5, T:ANDE
7          (A) [](+)-(_)-(+)-(                                                6, A:AOA
8          A                                                                          7, A:EED
where "(_)" is the empty structure (a structure that is always false). Line 6 is because we can write line 5 as: (A)-(+)-( )-(+)-(A) []-(+)-(_)-(+)-( AND (A)-(+)-( []-(+)-(A) []-(+)-(_)-(+)-(, since they have the same meaning.
  We prove Syllogism:
1    A -> B  B -> C                        Premise
2    (A -> B)->-(  (B -> C)->-(                    1, A:AtI
3    )->-(A)->-[]  (B)->-(  )->-(B) []->-(C)->-(            2, A:ADx2
4    (A)->-[] (B)->-(  )->-(B)  []->-(C)              3, A:ASS, A:SDx2, A:ASS
5    (A)->-[]  []->-(C)                        4, A:AA
6    (A)->-(  )->-(C)                        5, A:ASS
7    A -> C                                6, A:AL

      The primitive proposition of Principia Mathematica called "Sum." can be 
proven using a version of A:AA and the definition of "therefore". It needs a somewhat 
different version of A:AA stated as follows:


A:AAE: (P)->( Q )->(P) R <> Q R

  Theorem 2.0.11.2: ( P -> Q ) -> ((~R OR P) -> (~R OR Q))

Proof:

Line # Statement                                               Reason
1         P -> Q                                                   Premise
2         )->-(P) []->-(Q)->-(                               1, A:AtI, A:AD
3        (R)->-( )->-(P) )->-(R) []->-(Q)->-(       2, A:AAE
4        (R->P) )->-(R) []->-(Q)->-(                  3, A:AL
5        (R->P) []->-(R) )->-(Q)                        4, A:ASS, A:SD
6        (R->P) []->-(R)->(Q)                           5, T:AL
7        (R->P) []->-((R)->(Q))                         6, See text
8        (R->P) )->-((R)->(Q))                          7, A:ASS
9        (R->P)->(R->Q)                                 8, T:AL
10      (~R OR P)->(~R OR Q)                        9, Def. of ->

where "See text" is: because the other priority assignment is refuted by the 
refuted axiom that follows:
RA:TP:  ... []->-(R)->(Q) X<> (... []->-(R))->(Q)
where "X" means "not".
end

Edited by talanum46
minor errors
Posted

Well, wadda ya know, proof that a paradox can't exist, congratulations on your logical side of reason, where x = bollox...

Guest
This topic is now closed to further replies.
×
×
  • Create New...

Important Information

We have placed cookies on your device to help make this website better. You can adjust your cookie settings, otherwise we'll assume you're okay to continue.